Law in Contemporary Society

Moral and Philosophical Bearings for a Law Student's Future Direction

-- By JustineHong - 11 Mar 2022

Introduction

Holmes underscores that the law does not reflect morality, but instead constitutes a study of predicting court decisions. While one may believe, therefore, that philosophers have little role in developing a lawyer’s theory of social action, Hannah Arendt and Roberto Unger’s theories, while expressing a moral purpose, also reflect the socio-historical realities of the modern era. Because they are grounded in such realities, their moral and ethical principles are relevant in guiding lawyers in their practice. For instance, Arendt’s principle in Origins of Totalitarianism that a state or community must recognize fundamental rights in order for them to exist motivated me to develop my interest in human rights and international law. Also, Unger’s principle in Law in Modern Society that the solution to today’s unjust social inequalities is an expansion of access to intellectual capital motivates my own goal of expanding educational opportunities for others. Ultimately, the works of both Arendt and Unger urge lawyers to look beyond legal doctrine and toward the social interests and public policy which shape law in contemporary society.

Arendt: State Recognition of Fundamental Rights

Origins of Totalitarianism expresses the key principle that human rights, far from being “natural,” require state recognition to exist. In particular, the “calamity of the rightless . . . is not that they are not equal before the law, but that no law exists for them . . . We become aware of a right to have rights” (Arendt 295-7). In other words, unless a person belongs in a community like a state, he or she cannot not have “fundamental” rights like life, liberty, or equal protection before the law.

Arendt’s account, in addition to contextualizing my prior exposure to human rights, motivated my decision to explore international law. Before reading Arendt, in high school I had volunteered as an English oral translator at the House of Sharing, a museum and refuge in South Korea for the former ‘comfort women’ of WWII. Arendt's account made me realize that their plight illustrated the extreme experiences of stateless people. Believing such atrocities should never recur, I developed my interest in international law as an undergraduate, conducting independent study of the Nuremberg Trials and spending a summer abroad with EU institutions. An underlying motivation throughout these experiences was that no one should struggle to have the right to have rights. In law school, I will continue to consider international legal issues with Arendt’s principle in mind.

Unger: Modern Estrangement of Morality from Law

Like Arendt, Unger emphasizes the estrangement of morality from law and from the modern social order. Upon showing the historical trend in which the rule of law became devoid of moral justification in liberal societies, Law in Modern Society articulates the resulting principle that for many people today, the pursuit of the good fails to align with the pursuit of profit. This principle is the consequence of the widespread perception that social inequality is arbitrary, and that social consensus is merely the product of dominant interest groups, rather than any inherent justice (Unger 169).

The Knowledge Economy as a Solution

According to Unger, a solution for such arbitrary inequalities is the expansion of the “knowledge economy," a system of consumption and production based on intellectual capital, such as the value of its workers' knowledge or intellectual property. Although it is the most innovative way to organize economic activity, the knowledge economy remains trapped in small segments of the population. Ways to expand it include a reorganization of capital and other means of production, more collaborative relations among workers and superiors, and educational reform.

Unger’s account of the knowledge economy motivates my desire to contribute to its expansion. As a first-generation law student and American, I attribute my current status in large part to my access to intellectual capital. Furthermore, my parents transcended class through education; they are both first-generation college students who grew up under South Korea’s military dictatorship lasting until 1988. About a decade later, they were able to move to the US for a job opportunity. Therefore, as part of a family which transcended class and national barriers largely thanks to education, I am sensitive to the need to expand the knowledge economy.

However, I am also aware of potential difficulties. Because there are no lawyers in my family, I lack a professional network in either Korea or the US, apart from fellow law students and several non-lawyer family friends. Hence, I fear that no one would be able to provide assistance if I were to establish my own practice. Prior to law school, I was excited to forge my own path; indeed, I was motivated to apply primarily because no one encouraged me to do so and no one around me was a lawyer. But, after 1L year, I am more hesitant to establish my own practice, at least immediately after graduation, because of the overwhelming 1L curriculum and the administration’s clear division between Big Law and public interest, with nothing in between. My goal is that with the infantilizing 1L year over, I will develop a more coherent idea about my future. Above all, given my own background, Unger’s account reinforces my belief that lawyers should give back to their communities by facilitating access to intellectual capital.

Conclusion

Arendt and Unger present alternative philosophic principles to guide a law student’s future practice. Arendt’s argument that human rights are meaningless without the recognition of a state contextualized my own experience with human rights victims and motivated my interest in international law. On the other hand, Unger’s argument highlighting the estrangement of morality from the rule of law, the consequent social inequality, and the expansion of the knowledge economy as a solution to these issues motivates my goal of contributing to such a solution in my practice, even if that means diverging from the majority path. Overall, although both theorists are primarily concerned with philosophy rather than social science, their theories still provide guideposts with which to forge a legal practice.


You are entitled to restrict access to your paper if you want to. But we all derive immense benefit from reading one another's work, and I hope you won't feel the need unless the subject matter is personal and its disclosure would be harmful or undesirable. To restrict access to your paper simply delete the "#" character on the next two lines:

Note: TWiki has strict formatting rules for preference declarations. Make sure you preserve the three spaces, asterisk, and extra space at the beginning of these lines. If you wish to give access to any other users simply add them to the comma separated ALLOWTOPICVIEW list.

Navigation

Webs Webs

r8 - 07 Jun 2022 - 13:15:05 - JustineHong
This site is powered by the TWiki collaboration platform.
All material on this collaboration platform is the property of the contributing authors.
All material marked as authored by Eben Moglen is available under the license terms CC-BY-SA version 4.
Syndicate this site RSSATOM